VARIABLES AFFECTING TELEOLOGICAL REFLECTIVE SENSE FORMATION IN ENGLISH POLITICAL DISCOURSE

Keywords: teleological semantics, qualitative analysis, «deep» comprehension, ultimate explanation, heuristics, intuitive truth-values, ascription of sense

Abstract

Why is it so that people using the same language, identical words, phrases, sentences with reference to the same conceptual entity do not understand each other, and cannot agree on seemingly the same idea? It looks like the spectre of the archetypal Tower of Babel looms over any issue associated with political discourse today. It is not only the problem of merely linguistic confusion. The quandary of the mismatch between the ‘speaker’s meaning’ and the ‘recovered meaning’ may acquire menacing proportions especially in situations when politicians have to grapple with existential threats like social stand-offs, international crises, military conflicts, etc. No wonder then that the problem of understanding, interpretation and evaluation is of vital importance for further advances in the artificial intelligence domain. Realising this, the developers are struggling to equip AI with ‘teleological threads’, with human- like ‘world knowledge’, and with the awareness of the final goal (‘Telos’). This enquiry is focused on the ‘ultimate explanation’ of meaning of an utterance in political discourse relying on the terminological apparatus and methodology of teleological semantics. A qualitative research design and some elements of correlation methods to assess the relationships between and among variables were used in this research. The factors which may affect, transform, or pervert the meaning of an utterance are posited in this account as qualitative variables.The initial assumption of this study is that the concept of the common «GOOD» as the final goal («Telos») and the intended purpose of any social and political activity functions as the catalyst of teleological reflective sense attribution. «Telos» determines the semantic relationship among variables and is viewed as a dependent outcome variable and as a consequent whose semantic content is affected by independent variables functioning as antecedents. The aim of this enquiry is to identify a set of variables potentially involved in teleological reflective sense formation, to determine their types, semantically relevant characteristics and semantic correlation patterns between independent and dependent variables. The empirical material used in this research is a corpus of topically related comments as linguistic representations of teleological reflection on current political issues highlighted in the British press. The nomenclature of variables involved in teleological reflective sense attribution in political discourse is determined by the selective nature of human perception, and by the principles of causality, purposefulness, and intended consequences.The formalised propositional model is suggested using sentential logic conditional formula for the analysis of the semantically relevant correlation among intervening, moderator, predictor, proxy variables. The variables concerned highlight the cause and effect relationship between the dependent variable «Telos» and the independent variables. A group of autochthonous variables reflecting individual dispositions of speakers in political discourse has been identified. They are preferences, attitudes, obsessions, biases.

References

1. Aristotle. (1999). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by W.D. Ross. Batoche Books. Kitchener. 182 pp.
2. Bach, K. (2006). Language, Logic, and Form. A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Dale Jacquette (ed.). Oxford : Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Pp. 51–72.
3. Baur, N. (2007). Variable. The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology. George Ritzer (ed.). Oxford : Blackwell Publishing. Pp. 5184–5187.
4. Bostrom, N. (2017). Superintelligence. Paths, Dangers, Strategies. Oxford : Oxford University Press. 415 pp.
5. Buchanan I. (2018). A Dictionary of Critical Theory. 2nd ed. Oxford : Oxford University Press. 517 pp.
6. Chandler, D., Munday, R. (2020). A Dictionary of Media and Communication. 3rd ed. Oxford : Oxford University Press. 544 pp.
7. Colman, A.M. (2015). The Oxford Dictionary of Psychology. 4th ed. Oxford : Oxford University Press. 883 pp.
8. Devitt, M., Sterelny, K. (1999). Language and Reality. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. 2nd ed. Oxford : Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 342 pp.
9. Eisenstein, J. (2019). Introduction to Natural Language Processing. Cambridge, MA : The MIT Press. 519 pp.
10. Emerson, R.W. (1913). Essays and Representative Men. The Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson. Vol. 1. London : G. Bell and Sons, Ltd. 513 pp.
11. Evans, V. (2019). Cognitive Linguistics: A Complete Guide. 2nd ed. Edinburgh : Edinburgh Uni- versity Press. 896 pp.
12. Forbes, G. (1994). Modern Logic. A Text in Elementary Symbolic Logic. New York, Oxford : Oxford University Press. 397 pp.
13. Kant I. (1987). Critique of Judgement. Transl. by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis, Cambridge : Hackett Publishing Company. 576 pp.
14. Koertge, N. (2006). Social Sciences. The Philosophy of Science. An Encyclopedia. Sahotra Sarkar and Jessica Pfeifer eds. New York, London : Routledge, Tailor & Francis Group. Pp. 780–785.
15. Mathiesen, K. (2005). Collective Consciousness. Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson (eds.). Oxford : Oxford University Press. Pp. 235–250.
16. Matthews, P.H. (2014). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Linguistics. Oxford : Oxford University Press. 443 pp.
17. Mautner. T. (2005). The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy. 2nd ed. London : Penguin Books. 664 pp.
18. O,Hear, A. (1987). What Philosophy Is. An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy. Advisory editor Ted Honderich. Harmondsworth : Penguin Books Ltd. 316 pp.
19. Partee, B.H. (2020). Changing Notion of Linguistic Competence in the History of Formal Semantics. The Science of Meaning. Essays on the Metatheory of Natural Language Semantics. Derek Ball and Brian Rabern (eds.). Oxford : Oxford University Press. Pp. 172–196.
20. Quine W.V. (1960). Variables Explained Away. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, Vol. 104, No. 3, pp. 343–347.
21. Reber, A.S., Allen, R., Reber, E S. (2009). The Penguin Dictionary of Psychology. 4th ed. London : Penguin Books. 904 pp.
22. Recanati, F. (2003). Literal Meaning. Cambridge : Cambridge University Press. 235 pp.
23. Seuren P.A.M. (1998). Western Linguistics: An Historical Introduction. Oxford : Blackwell Pub- lishers. 570 pp.
24. Siewert, C. (2005). Attention and Sensorimotor Intentionality. Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson (eds.). Oxford : Oxford University Press. Pp. 270–294.
25. Smith, D.W. (2005). Consciousness with Reflex- ive Content. Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Tho- masson (eds.). Oxford : Oxford University Press. Pp. 93–114.
26. The Daily Mail. 2024. 4 August.
27. Verhagen, A. (2007). Construal and Perspec- tivization. The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics. Dirk Geeraerts and Hubert Cuyck- ens (eds.). Oxford : Oxford University Press. Pp. 48–81.
Published
2025-07-01
How to Cite
Shevchenko, O. I. (2025). VARIABLES AFFECTING TELEOLOGICAL REFLECTIVE SENSE FORMATION IN ENGLISH POLITICAL DISCOURSE. New Philology, (98), 193-202. https://doi.org/10.26661/2414-1135-2025-98-24
Section
Articles